\(\DeclarePairedDelimiterX{\Set}[2]{\{}{\}}{#1 \nonscript\;\delimsize\vert\nonscript\; #2}\) \( \DeclarePairedDelimiter{\set}{\{}{\}}\) \( \DeclarePairedDelimiter{\parens}{\left(}{\right)}\) \(\DeclarePairedDelimiterX{\innerproduct}[1]{\langle}{\rangle}{#1}\) \(\newcommand{\ip}[1]{\innerproduct{#1}}\) \(\newcommand{\bmat}[1]{\left[\hspace{2.0pt}\begin{matrix}#1\end{matrix}\hspace{2.0pt}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\barray}[1]{\left[\hspace{2.0pt}\begin{matrix}#1\end{matrix}\hspace{2.0pt}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\mat}[1]{\begin{matrix}#1\end{matrix}}\) \(\newcommand{\pmat}[1]{\begin{pmatrix}#1\end{pmatrix}}\) \(\newcommand{\mathword}[1]{\mathop{\textup{#1}}}\)
Needs:
Ordered Pairs
Needed by:
None.
Links:
Sheet PDF
Graph PDF

Ordered Pair Pathologies

Why

Why define ordered pairs in terms of sets? Why not make them their own intangible object?

Pathologies

Notice that $a \not\in (a, b)$ and similarly $b \not\in (a, b)$. These facts led us to use the terms first and second “coordinate” in Ordered Pairs rather than the term “element” (used in Sets). Neither $a$ nor $b$ is an element of the ordered pair $(a, b)$. On the other hand, it is true that $\set{a} \in (a, b)$ and $(a, b) \in (a, b)$. These facts are odd. Should they bother us?

We chose to define ordered pairs in terms of sets so that we could reuse notions about a particular type of object (sets) that we had already developed. We chose what we may call conceptual simplicty (reusing notions from sets) over defining a new type of object (the ordered pair) with its own primitive properties. Taking the former path, rather than the latter is a matter of taste, really, and not a logical consequence of the nature of things.

The argument for our taste is as follows. We already know about sets, so let's use them, and let's forget cases like $(a, b) \in (a, b)$ (called by some authors “pathologies”). It does not bother us that our construction admits many true (but irrelevant) statements. Such is the case in life.

Suppose we did choose to make the object $(a, b)$ primitive. Sure, we would avoid oddities like $\set{a} \in (a, b)$. And we might even get statements like $a \in (a, b)$ to be true. But to do so we would have to define the meaning of $\in$ for the case in which the right hand object is an “ordered pair”. Our current route avoids introducing any new concepts, and simply names a construction using already developed concepts.

Copyright © 2023 The Bourbaki Authors — All rights reserved — Version 13a6779cc About Show the old page view