\(\DeclarePairedDelimiterX{\Set}[2]{\{}{\}}{#1 \nonscript\;\delimsize\vert\nonscript\; #2}\) \( \DeclarePairedDelimiter{\set}{\{}{\}}\) \( \DeclarePairedDelimiter{\parens}{\left(}{\right)}\) \(\DeclarePairedDelimiterX{\innerproduct}[1]{\langle}{\rangle}{#1}\) \(\newcommand{\ip}[1]{\innerproduct{#1}}\) \(\newcommand{\bmat}[1]{\left[\hspace{2.0pt}\begin{matrix}#1\end{matrix}\hspace{2.0pt}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\barray}[1]{\left[\hspace{2.0pt}\begin{matrix}#1\end{matrix}\hspace{2.0pt}\right]}\) \(\newcommand{\mat}[1]{\begin{matrix}#1\end{matrix}}\) \(\newcommand{\pmat}[1]{\begin{pmatrix}#1\end{pmatrix}}\) \(\newcommand{\mathword}[1]{\mathop{\textup{#1}}}\)
Needs:
Measures
Real Limits
Needed by:
Almost Everywhere Measurability
Almost Sure Events
Iterated Integrals
Links:
Sheet PDF
Graph PDF

Negligible Sets

Why

Some apparently reasonable statements do not hold for all elements of the base set of a measurable space. Even so, these statements often hold broadly, in the sense that the measure of the set on which they fail is zero.

This idea allows one to handle statements which fail on a set of measure zero as if they held everywhere. This approach is useful in discussions of convergence and integration.

Definition

For this sheet, suppose $(X, \mathcal{A} , \mu )$ is a measure space. Call a set $N \subset X$ negligible if there exists a measurable set $A \in \mathcal{A} $ with $\mu (A) = 0$ and $N \subset A$. In english, there is a measurable set containing $N$ that has measure zero.

The qualification “if there exists a measurable set...” enables one to speak of nonmeasurable negligible sets. Negligible sets need not be measurable.

Given the measure $\mu $, a statement $s$ holds almost everywhere with respect to $\mu $ if the set of elements on which the statement fails is negligible. In symbols, there exists $A \in \mathcal{A} $ with $\mu (A) = 0$ and

\[ \Set{x \in X}{\neg s(x)} \subset A \]

A statement which holds “everywhere” holds “almost everywhere” also. With this in mind, we call the almost everywhere sense “weaker” than the everywhere sense.

Notation

We abbreviate almost everywhere as “a.e.,” read “almost everywhere”. We say that a statement “holds a.e.” If the measure $\mu $ is not clear from context, we say that the property holds almost everywhere $[\mu ]$ or $\mu $-a.e., read “mu almost everywhere.”

Function comparisons

Let $f, g: X \to \R $, not necessarily measurable. Then $f = g$ almost everywhere if the set of points at which the functions disagree is $\mu $-negligible. Similarly, $f \geq g$ almost everywhere if the set of points where $f$ is less than $g$ is $\mu $-negligible.

If $f$ and $g$ were both in fact $\mathcal{A} $-measurable, then the sets

\[ \Set*{x \in X}{f(x) \neq g(x)} \text{ and } \Set*{x \in X}{f(x) < g(x)} \]

would be measurable also. But in general, these sets need not be measurable, and so this is one simple example to justify our including nonmeasurable sets in the definition of neglible sets, as mentioned above.

Function limits

Let $\seqt{f}: X \to R$ for each natural number $n$ and let $f: X \to R$ be a function. The sequence $\seq{f}$ converges to $f$ almost everywhere if

\[ \Set*{x \in X}{\lim_{n} \seqt{f}(x) \text{ does not exist, or } f(x) \neq \lim_{n} \seqt{f}(x)} \]

is $\mu $-negligible. In this case, we write “$f = \lim_n \seqt{f}$ a.e.”

Copyright © 2023 The Bourbaki Authors — All rights reserved — Version 13a6779cc About Show the old page view